Topic > The Negative Impacts of Science Demonstrated by Friedrich Nietzshe

In The Gay Science, Friedrich Nietzsche criticizes the limits and possibilities of modern science. In this critique, Nietzsche analyzes the limits of science, the ways in which science falsifies life, and the motivation for a scientific pursuit of knowledge. Although Nietzsche does not categorically reject the potential of science, he is extremely skeptical about its modern use. His skepticism arises from what he believes is science's fundamental problem: that it can describe the motion of particles, but cannot explain human behavior. To explore this issue, Nietzsche uses a unique approach that is decidedly against science. Rather than approaching concepts in literal terms or hypotheses, he uses an interrogative method and irreverent style to aggressively challenge the value of a purely scientific worldview and offer his own “gay science.” Say no to plagiarism. Get a tailor-made essay on "Why Violent Video Games Shouldn't Be Banned"? Get an original essay Nietzsche's criticism is particularly interested in what he believes are the limits of science. He argues that a fundamental limitation of science is its limited ability to interpret. Science, Nietzsche argues, is alarming because of the emphasis it places on the “external aspect of existence” (Nietzsche 335). He believes that before science “philosophers were afraid of the senses,” but now “we all believe in [them]” (332). This belief is present in modern scientists who “do scientific research with their senses” to provide “an interpretation that allows them to count, calculate, weigh, see, touch, and nothing more” (335). Reducing everything to an interpretation that only admits what the senses can perceive neglects what Nietzsche believes are the individual's much greater faculties of reflection, understanding and understanding. He argues that a purely scientific interpretation that neglects such faculties might be "one of the stupidest of all possible interpretations of the world" as it "would be one of the poorest in meaning" (335). He gives the example of a scientific interpretation of music to illustrate his point. While it was possible to “estimate the value of a piece of music by how much of it could be counted, calculated, and expressed in formulas,” it would be an “absurd estimate” that would not be “understood, comprehended, or grasped… whatever let there be music [in the piece]” (336). Art, like existence, is more than numbers and calculations. It is an equivocal and ambiguous experience that resists the constraints of a single interpretation. Nietzsche also believes that science is limited in its ability to explain. Although science seeks to offer explanations, Nietzsche argues that all science provides us with better descriptions of the world around us. He points to the scientific process of cause and effect as an example. Scientists use cause and effect to deduce that “this and that must precede so that this or that can then follow” (172). However, this process “involves no understanding” (172). Although a relationship is drawn between two things in cause and effect, scientists have “simply perfected the image of becoming without going beyond the image or behind it” (172). For example, scientists may use cause and effect to describe how one chemical reacts with another chemical to form a reaction, but the “quality [of the reaction] appears like a miracle” (172). Scientists cannot explain why the reaction produces the effects it does without resorting to things they themselves invented – things like “lines, planes, bodies, atoms, divisible intervals of time, [and] divisible space” (172). All attempts at scientific explanationthey are therefore only attempts to «make an image of everything[,] our image» (172). Science cannot provide a true explanation of human experience. Rather, it allows us to “describe ourselves more and more precisely” (173). The limitations that Nietzsche identifies in science are central to his critique of science as something that falsifies human life. Nietzsche sees science as something that contradicts much of what it means to be human. Science attempts to create a “world of truth that can be mastered completely and forever with the help of…reason” (335). However, such a world in Nietzsche's mind “would allow existence to be degraded to…a mere exercise for a calculator” (335). This world would “strip existence of its rich ambiguity,” creating “a world essentially devoid of meaning” (335). The things that Nietzsche claims make us human – our inability to know the truth, the “volubility of [our existence]” (111), our “freedom above things” (164) – are rejected by science. Science claims a truth, denies the variability of existence and limits itself to the study of things. Nietzsche argues that by denying these aspects of authentic existence, science falsifies life. Nietzsche argues that science also falsifies life by denying the idea of ​​multiple interpretations of existence. He argues that a fundamental aspect of human existence is the question of how far “the perspectival character of [our] existence extends” (336). In other words, Nietzsche asks whether there is a limit to human interpretive abilities. He argues that this question is unanswerable, since “the human intellect cannot avoid seeing itself in its own perspectives and in these [perspectives] alone” (336). We cannot separate ourselves from our existence and therefore we cannot define how far the prospective character of our existence extends. As a result of this inability, Nietzsche rejects the “ridiculous immodesty that…decrees that perspectives are permitted only from one angle” and states that “we cannot reject the possibility that [the world] may include infinite interpretations” (336). Science, however, does both. It decrees that only scientific interpretations are permissible and rejects the idea of ​​multiple interpretations. Science's claim to allow humans to separate themselves from perspective and provide a single objective interpretation falsifies what Nietzsche sees as another fundamental characteristic of life: the possibility of infinite interpretations of existence. Nietzsche argues that the final way in which science falsifies life is in its failure to consider the value of human life. Nietzsche sees human existence as something that has fundamental value, but science cannot take it into account. Rather, it reduces life to actions and reactions and places value only on a single objective truth. Scientists claim that “nothing is more necessary than the truth, and in relation to it everything else has only second-rate value” (281). However, Nietzsche argues that placing value on truth is a human action: everything that has value in our world "has no value in itself, but [has been] valued at some time" (242). Science cannot take into account the human ability to create or evaluate value. It treats the human being as “spectator and listener” and denies the human being the outlet to “create [his] own life” (241). Since science cannot consider the value of human life and claims a single truth, it “affirms a world other than that of life” (282). By affirming this world, science “denies its counterpart” (283) – our world – and falsifies life. Although Nietzsche is critical of science, he is still interested in what motivates researchof knowledge in the discipline. He argues that the primary motivation behind the scientific pursuit of knowledge is the “demand for certainty” (282). Unlike philosophy, science satisfies the individual's desire for a single correct truth. Science provides “great certainty” and takes “something strange and reduces it to something familiar” (301). It satisfies the individual's “unconditional will to truth” and appears to prevent the individual from being deceived (281). Nietzsche asks why the individual attributes such value to truth. He compares this absolute faith in truth to faith in religion. Science claims that truth is right because deception is wrong, but this is just a moral statement. In this sense, science is motivated by a “metaphysical faith” in truth that is comparable to a religious faith in God. Nietzsche argues that even the scientific pursuit of knowledge is motivated by weakness. Like faith in religion, faith in science is “most desired and most urgently needed where the will is lacking” (289). Those who lack will have “sovereignty and strength” and rely on these faiths to provide structure for how they should live their lives (289). Science satisfies those who are “distrustful and evil” (104) by providing them with what appears to be certainty. Nietzsche also suggests that the motivation to pursue science is a reaction to boredom. He states that "those who have too much free time don't know what to do with it except reading, collecting, organizing, observing, and telling: their scientific impulse is their boredom" (179). In both cases, science satisfies those who lack the “willpower” to define their own existence and satisfy their desire for certainty (179). Nietzsche's criticism of science is reflected in his approach to its criticism. One of his general criticisms of science is that it lacks conviction. In a scientific approach to knowledge, a belief is permitted only when it “reduces itself to the modesty of hypotheses” or to “a provisional experimental point of view” (280). In essence, a belief in the scientific approach is permitted only when it “ceases to be a belief” (280). In contrast, Nietzsche's approach to knowledge can be seen as pure belief. Unlike a scientific method devoid of will, Nietzsche's method is driven by “the will to question further, more deeply, severely, harshly, wickedly, and silently than has been questioned thus far” (36). Through this aggressively questioning method, Nietzsche attempts to offer his readers a new and disconcerting perspective on conventions and propriety that forces them to look at common things in a new light. This method is in direct conflict with science. Nietzsche does not feel the need to demonstrate everything he does; rather, it eschews data, mathematics, and evidence in favor of a “belief in forms, tones, and words” (38) and a willingness to question. Nietzsche's questioning method manifests itself in a unique style that also opposes science. He emphasizes the need for all individuals to “give style to their character” (232). Individuals, he argues, should “examine all the strengths and weaknesses of their nature and then fit them into an artistic plan until each appears as art and reason” (232). In other words, Nietzsche argues that we develop our style when we combine our characteristics and integrate our traits, habits, and actions. The importance he places on developing his own style is evident in his unique style. Unlike other philosophers of his time, Nietzsche refuses to address philosophical concepts in direct terms. Constantly questions the logic behind beliefs, values ​​and:.